The Trouble with Epigenetics (Part 1)
“You keep using that
word. I do not think it means what you think it means”. The insightful Inigo Montoya.
Epigenetics is a word
that seems to have caught the public imagination. This is especially true among
those, both in science and without, who decry what they see as genetic
determinism or at least an overly “genocentric” point of view. Our genes are
not our fate, because epigenetics! Such-and-such disorder is not really
genetic, because epigenetics! Acquired characteristics can be inherited,
because epigenetics!
The trouble with
epigenetics is that the word means very different things in different contexts.
Each of them may be quite valid, but when these meanings are conflated or when
the intended meaning is not specified, the word becomes dangerously ambiguous.
This is especially evident in the fields of behavioural and psychiatric
research where the term is much abused, often, it seems to me, to give an air
of mechanistic truthiness to ideas that are in reality both speculative and vague.
Originally coined by Conrad Waddington in his famous “epigenetic landscape”, the word signified the
emergence of the eventual phenotype of an organism through the processes of
development, starting from a particular genetic profile. It was derived from
Aristotle’s term “epigenesis”, which means pretty much the same thing – that
organisms emerge through a program of development, as opposed to the theory of
preformationism (where a teeny organism is already formed inside an egg and
simply grows). Waddington’s new term incorporated the idea of a genetic
profile, which shapes the metaphorical landscape over which each individual developing
organism travels, channeling them with greater or lesser probability toward
certain outcomes. The epigenetic landscape was intended to show that the
relationship between genotype and phenotype is non-linear and probabilistic,
not deterministic. This importantly incorporates effects of chance or the
environment on the eventual outcome.
A newer definition arose
with the growth of molecular biology. Here, epigenetics refers to mechanisms of
gene regulation that determine the state of a cell and that are heritable
through cell divisions but that do not involve changes in DNA sequence.
Essentially, this means all the processes that make one cell of an organism
different from another, that keep it that way and that allow that state to be
passed on to that cell’s descendants. It is often more specifically used to refer
to chemical modifications (such as methylation or acetylation) of DNA or of the
histone proteins associated with it in chromatin. These epigenetic marks can
affect gene expression and can be stably inherited from one cell to another
(i.e., through mitotic cell division).
This molecular biology
definition has really only a loose relationship to Waddington’s usage. It is
obviously true that molecular mechanisms of gene regulation effect (as in
mediate) the development of an organism. That is what cellular differentiation
and coordinated organismal development entail. Genes are turned on, genes are
turned off. Epigenetic mechanisms make the profiles of gene expression that
define a particular cell type more stable, with different sets of genes held in
active or inactive chromatin conformations. These two usages thus relate to
very different levels – one refers to the profile of gene expression of
individual cell types and the other to the emergence of the phenotype of the
organism.
Now, clearly, the
phenotype of an organism depends largely (though by no means completely) on the
profile of gene expression of its constituent cells. And there are indeed a
number of examples where the behavioural phenotype of an organism has been
linked to the epigenetic state of particular genes in cells in particular brain
regions. Importantly, such mechanisms may provide one means whereby
environmental factors or particular experiences can have long-lasting effects
on an organism, by changing patterns of gene expression in particular cells in
a stable manner.
This has been
demonstrated so far mainly in rodents, but in several different instances (reviewed here and here). These
include responses to maternal care, to various kinds of stressors, including
that caused by early maternal separation and to other experiences, notably drug exposure. In all of these instances, some environmental trigger or experience induces
a response in an animal. One aspect of this response is to alter the set point
of the system so that its response to subsequent events of the same type is
changed (i.e., learning). In some cases, this involves changes in gene
expression and epigenetic marks may help make such changes long-lasting.
The examples above
include several where pathways have been worked out in detail, which lead from
detection of some stimulus to changes in the chromatin state of specific genes,
which are involved in setting the responsiveness or gain of the system. (As in the adjacent figure, from Caldji et al., 2011, showing effects on methylation of the glucocorticoid receptor gene). These may well represent important mechanisms of biological memory for regulating
reactivity of various brain systems, which thus influence subsequent behaviour
in a long-lasting fashion.
Based on these kinds
of examples, epigenetics has become quite a buzz-word in the fields of
psychiatric and behavioural genetics, as if it provides a general molecular
mechanism for all the non-genetic factors that influence an individual’s phenotype.
Twin studies looking
at the heritability of psychiatric disorders or behavioural traits show a
consistent pattern: monozygotic twins are considerably more similar to each
other for these phenotypes than are dizygotic twins, but are usually not completely
identical. This demonstrates an effect of shared genes on phenotypic
resemblance (i.e., heritability) but also highlights the limits of that effect
– even genetically identical individuals are not phenotypically identical. Some
other, non-genetic factors must be contributing to the phenotype of an
individual and making monozygotic twins less similar to each other. But does
“non-genetic” necessarily mean “epigenetic”?
The fact that
environmental factors or extreme experiences can influence an organism’s
phenotype is not news. In specific cases like those described above, the
effects of such factors may indeed be mediated by molecular epigenetic
mechanisms. But here’s the important thing – even though epigenetic mechanisms
may be involved in maintaining some stable traits over the lifetime of the
animal, they are just that: mechanisms. Not causes. Epigenetics is not a source
of variance, it is part of the mechanism whereby certain environmental factors
or experiences have their effects. Furthermore, these few examples do not imply
that this mechanism is involved in mediating the effects of non-genetic sources
of variance more generally.
Differences in the
outcome of neural development can and do arise because the cellular events
controlling cell migration, axon guidance, synapse formation and other
developmental processes are inherently probabilistic. They are determined by
the interactions of thousands of different gene products and affected by intrinsic
noise at the levels of gene expression and molecular interactions between
proteins. The outcome is never the same twice. This is epigenetics in
Waddington’s usage – the emergence of a unique organism from a not necessarily
unique starting point (the genotype). There is no reason to think epigenetic mechanisms
of chromatin regulation are involved in these kinds of differences in neural
circuitry.
Note that there are
plenty of examples where mutations affecting proteins that mediate or regulate chromatin
states (such as MeCP2, CHD7, CHD8 and many others) cause neurodevelopmental
disorders such as intellectual disability, Rett syndrome and autism. But these
are genetic effects, which disrupt the epigenetic molecular machinery. That is,
the important difference between people in these instances is a good,
old-fashioned DNA mutation.
So, while epigenetic
mechanisms may indeed play a role in the stable expression of certain behavioural
tendencies (at least in rodents), it remains unclear how general this
phenomenon is. In any case, there is no reason to think of “epigenetics” as a
source or cause of phenotypic variance at the level of the organism. And here
is a plea: if you are tempted to use the term epigenetic, make it clear which
meaning you intend. If you simply mean non-genetic, there is a more precise
term for this: non-genetic.
In part 2, I consider a
more egregious trend emerging in the literature of late – the idea that
transgenerational epigenetic inheritance can provide a mechanism of heredity
that explains the so-called “missing heritability” of psychiatric disorders.
(It can’t).
Nice Perspective on things.
ReplyDeleteEpigenetic mechanisms are molecular mechanisms, just like synaptic transmission is a molecular mechanism: design is in the blue print.. look forward to Part II.
Thanks Shane. Yes, that's right - there's nothing revolutionary in the idea of epigenetics, it's just a mechanism of gene regulation, one that has been appreciated for a long time. Yet may people seem to think of it as a revolutionary new paradigm that overturns classical genetics.
DeleteGreat read.. For me, it's not that epigenetics overturns "classical" genetics in any way; rather, more from a scientific awareness perspective, it helps to highlight the influence of environment in the determination of the phenotype; something that we as a society often tend to ignore (when referring to, for instance, criminal behaviour, by the phrase "it's genetic")
DeleteInteresting overall, but I cannot understand two things. First, you say "There is no reason to think epigenetic mechanisms of chromatin regulation are involved in these kinds of differences in neural circuitry." Why not? Say a fetal germ cell is heavily exposed to synthetic steroid hormone drugs, resulting in aberrations in epigenetic programming resulting from the interference with germline reprogramming that occurs in the first half of gestation. Then, decades later, that germ cell joins with another (egg or sperm, as the case may be), resulting in profound neurodevelopmental abnormality/autism in the resulting child. Is that autism due to "noise" or to the ancestral exposure to the potent synthetic compound completely novel in the scheme of 4 billion years of evolution?
ReplyDeleteSecond, what's wrong with transgenerational epigenetic inheritance? If a fetal germcell (the F3 generation) is exposed and epigenetically altered, why wouldn't the F4 generation inherit the marks?
Thanks for your comments. Let me try and answer your two questions. First, I meant that epigenetic mechanisms are unlikely to be involved in mediating the kinds of differences in neural circuitry that emerge as a consequence of intrinsic variability in neurodevelopmental processes. Clearly, they can be involved in mediating some other kinds of effects, including environmental or experiential ones, like the examples I gave. The scenario you cite sounds reasonable enough, but then lots of things could happen - the question is what kinds of things do we actually have evidence for?
DeleteAs for what's wrong with transgenerational epigenetic inheritance, I will get to that in Part 2! (Coming as soon as I get some time to finish it).
Thanks, Kevin. What kind of things do we have evidence for? Work by Skinner, Crews, Gore, Rissman and others finds fetal germline perturbations caused by exposure to endocrine disrupting/synthetic hormone-mimicking compounds. And neurobehavioral consequences were found. So, again, are those consequences "noise" or did they result from the epigenetic impairment of the exposed germ cells?
DeleteI shall look forward to Part 2 -- I apologize for mislabeling the generations in my comment. The exposed fetal germcell is F2 (with F0 being the pregnant female and F1 the exposed fetus). I wonder why you think F3 would also not be affected by the exposure.
Klinefelter Syndrome is the most common genetic syndrome that occurs in males only. Klinefelter Syndrome is not inherited and 1 in 500 to 1,000 newborn male infants are diagnosed with Klinefelter Syndrome. The cause of Klinefelter Syndrome is an egg or sperm mutation that produces the XXY genotype. About half the cases are caused by an XY sperm mutation and half are caused by an XX egg mutation.
Deletehttp://ghr.nlm.nih.gov/condition/klinefelter-syndrome
The prevelance of XY sperm mutations increases with advancing paternal age. A few months ago McCAullife and co-workers discoverd that increasing levels of exposure to PCB congeners as measured in blood increased the production of XY sperm mutations.
http://www.ncbi.nlm.nih.gov/pubmed/11582569
http://www.ncbi.nlm.nih.gov/pmc/articles/PMC3339457/pdf/ehp.1104017.pdf
I'm not sure if you're implying that Klinefelter's somehow has an epigenetic mechanism? It doesn't. You've outlined the causes very clearly above and none involves epigenetics. Environmental mutagens causing mutations (or chromosomal non-disjunction) is not epigenetics.
DeleteNo doubt there is debate and argument over the definition of epigenetics and the contributions of epigenetics especially with respect to how does epigenetics produce human disease.
ReplyDeleteMy defintion of epigenetics comes from AIDS researchers. Common copy number variations in a single gene CCL3L1 located on chromosome 17q.21.1 is associated with HIV-1 infection risk. Copy number variations in this gene can be inherited or de novo. By itself CNV's in CCL3L1 does not appear to have any deliterious effect. Liu et al in a meta analysis found that lower copy numbers relative to population norms increases risk for infection while higher copy numbers relative to population norms confers protection against infection after exposure to the HIV-1 virus.
I would call this a classic example of how epigenetics works to produce human disease and even how epigenetics can work to prevent disease, What would you call this?
http://www.ncbi.nlm.nih.gov/pmc/articles/PMC3012711/
I would call that genetics.
DeleteI can't see why molecular epigenetic mechanism can't be a source of variance.
ReplyDeleteOnce a molecular epigenetic modification varies randomly (due to Waddington's epigenetics) it can become a source of variance in response to an environmental factor.
Yes, epigenetic mechanisms are clearly sources of variance. Chimps and humans share almost all the same protein-coding genes, the differences lie mainly how those genes are expressed via epigenetic mechanisms. Moreover, epigenetics are genetics function together, in a tight dance, and not separately. For example, methylation deserts caused by toxic exposures can destabilize DNA leading to higher risk for CNVs.
DeleteEpigenetic mechanisms can only be a source of variance if they vary. They sometimes do vary - due to mutations in components of the epigenetic machinery. Those are genetic effects. And if they are affected by environmental factors, then those are environmental effects - that is, epigenetics can provide a mechanism through which other factors have an effect but are not a source of variance in themselves - the variance comes from somewhere else.
DeleteLooking for answers in his DNA sequence to why Adam Lanza went on a rampage is absurd, offensive, idiotic, willfully ignorant, I could go on. I hope you're not suggesting it was epigenetics that made him do it!
ReplyDeleteThere is so much work and research that needs to be done here. So much has to be done to fix this all here. I hope to see it work in the future. Toronto Painters
ReplyDeleteGreat blog. All posts have something to learn. Your work is very good and i appreciate you and hoping for some more informative posts.
ReplyDeleteVacation
Home Wellbeing has a wide range of One Stop Home Essentials products that care for the wellbeing of You and Your Loved Ones.
ReplyDeleteThis blog post is highly informational and mature sufficient with its quality and layout in defining transcription facilities. Transcription serviceI will wait for more such educational posts in future
ReplyDeleteYour time is limited, so don't waste it living someone else's life. Don't be trapped by dogma - which is living with the results of other people's thinking. Don't let the noise of others' opinions drown out your own inner voice. And most important, have the courage to follow your heart and intuition.
ReplyDeleteNobis
Again, you can't connect the dots looking forward; you can only connect them looking backwards. So you have to trust that the dots will somehow connect in your future. You have to trust in something - your gut, destiny, life, karma, whatever. This approach has never let me down, and it has made all the difference in my life.
ReplyDeletehome theater installation houston tx
Again, you can't connect the dots looking forward; you can only connect them looking backwards. So you have to trust that the dots will somehow connect in your future. You have to trust in something - your gut, destiny, life, karma, whatever. This approach has never let me down, and it has made all the difference in my life.
ReplyDeleteParajumpers Jackets
Take up one idea. Make that one idea your life - think of it, dream of it, live on that idea. Let the brain, muscles, nerves, every part of your body, be full of that idea, and just leave every other idea alone. This is the way to success.
ReplyDeleteprivate plates
I'm an optimist in the sense that I believe humans are noble and honorable, and some of them are really smart. I have a very optimistic view of individuals.
ReplyDeletegrappige filmpjes
Amazing, So much wonderful sense can be reflected in this blog, Thanks for sharing rental mobil semarang
ReplyDeleteIt's interesting to see how buzz is created from only a partial or selective understanding of the underlying science. There are supplement companies who have cherry-picked portions of studies in which certain micronutrients were shown to increase telomere length, combined that w evidence of longer telomeres being correlated to longevity and created magical meal-replacement drinks which contain those micronutrients and then claim that consuming their shakes may help you live longer. Astounding leaps of logic abound in the self-help and supplement industries.
ReplyDeleteLoved reading this! I've hade this feelings for a time that there's a problem with how epigenetics is suddenly seen as the answer to all questions regarding environmental effects on the organism. Beeing an ethologist I feel that there is more to learning and behavior than different gene expressions. I think you pin point some of this in this post. Thanks so much for this. Do you have suggestions for further reading on this topic?
ReplyDelete