Debunking the male-female brain mosaic
There is no such thing as a male brain, or
a female brain. Instead, our brains are all really a mosaic of male and female
parts – we all have an “intersex” brain. This is the claim made by psychologist
Daphna Joel and colleagues, based mostly on a 2015 neuroimaging study in
humans, but also some previous work in rodents. This idea – especially the
catchy phrasing – has caught the public imagination and it has been widely
covered in the media. Indeed, a recent editorial in Scientific American,
entitled “The New Science of Sex and Gender”, cited this study as support for
the view that “To varying extents, many of us are
biological hybrids on a male-female continuum”. But
what do the data actually show? I will argue below that the interpretation of a
male-female mosaic is conceptually mistaken and based on a straw-man argument.
I’ve discussed these findings and their
interpretation before, as an illustration of how the same data can be used to
support diametrically opposite viewpoints. Here I want to consider a related
point – how framing a research question from a certain perspective colours the
conclusions that you draw from a study. In this case, the framing is wrong from
the outset.
This description of the study and its
findings is taken from my previous blogpost:
Daphna Joel and
colleagues analysed MRI scans of 169 females and 112 males, and segmented them
into 116 regions using a standard brain atlas. By analysing how much warping
was required to map each brain onto a reference template, it was possible to
compare the relative grey matter volume of all these regions across the two
sexes. From this group comparison the 10 regions showing the largest sex
differences were chosen for subsequent analyses.
So far, so good: the
primary finding is that there are statistically significant group
differences between males and females in grey matter volume across many
brain regions. That’s nothing new – a recent meta-analysis of 167 studies confirms consistent
group sex differences in many brain areas between men and women.
The authors went on,
however, to ask what could have been a more interesting question: across those
10 regions, how “male” or “female” were the structures of individual brains?
This is where the subjectivity comes in – there are many ways to analyse these
data and the authors chose arguably the most simplistic and extreme one, which
enabled them to draw the conclusion that male and female brains are not
categorically different.
They report that: “35%
percent of brains showed substantial variability, and only 6% of brains were
internally consistent”. Importantly they chose to classify only those
subjects showing extreme male or female values for all 10 regions
as “internally consistent”.
So, why did the authors choose those
criteria, scoring only the extreme values of these parameters? In a 2017
circumspective, co-written with Margaret McCarthy, Joel states:
In recent years I have been attempting to answer
whether sex differences in the brain
“add up‟ to create two types of brains, “male” and “female”. For this to be true the effects of sex
should be dimorphic, that
is, result in the formation of distinct “male” and “female” types, and internally consistent, that is, that all
elements of a single brain are either
“male” or “female”.
Are these two criteria valid? For “male”
brains and “female” brains to be a thing, must the differences between them
really be dimorphic? That is, not just a difference in degree, but in kind, like
the difference between male and female genitalia, which come in two clearly
different forms. Well, no. There is no reason to set that as the criterion.
An analogy with faces makes this clear.
Male and female faces differ on a wide range of parameters – size of the jaw,
prominence of the ridge over the eyebrows, fullness of the lips, size of the
bridge of the nose, and others (think Jason Momoa versus Natalie Portman). For each of these parameters, there is not a
male form and a female form – there is a distribution, which is shifted one way
in males and the other way in females. None of these markers by itself provides
the means to accurately classify faces as either male or female. But taking all
of them together certainly does. We are all very good at telling whether a face
is male or female and computer programs can also very successfully perform this
classification. So, “male” faces and “female” faces are clearly real things,
even though the differences in specific parameters between them are not
dimorphic.
(Figure credit: from https://clinicalgate.com/aesthetic-contouring-of-the-craniofacial-skeleton/)
The first criterion thus seems to be far
too strict – brains may differ on many individual parameters, between males and
females, due to a shift in an underlying distribution, rather than coming in two
discrete forms. And the second criterion thereby also falls – if these
distributions overlap, then you cannot score any individual region as being
either “male” or “female” and the idea of assessing internal consistency on
such a basis makes no sense.
Joel clearly acknowledges this fact, in a
2011 review:
There
are only a few brain characteristics for which the term sexually dimorphic,
which literally means having two forms, is appropriate, that is, for which
there is minimal or no overlap between the form of this characteristic in males
and females (e.g., the size of the sexually dimorphic nucleus of the preoptic
area, which is three to eight times larger in male rats compared to female
rats, Swaab, 1995). For most documented sex differences in the brain, however,
and in particular in regions involved in behavior, emotion, and cognition,
there is a considerable overlap between the distributions of the two sexes.
That’s all very accurate, and you could say
it is Joel’s main point, and an important and completely valid one. But Joel
goes on, immediately afterwards, to claim that:
It
follows, that individuals may have the “female” or the “male” form for any of
these non-dimorphic characteristics.
What? No! It totally doesn’t follow at all.
The previous sentences clearly establish that “female” or “male” forms DO NOT
EXIST.
Joel continues: The question then becomes whether the brain of a given individual is
homogenous or heterogeneous with respect to the “male/female” type of its brain
characteristics.
This is the straw man (or straw person)
argument. If most sex differences are not really dimorphic, then the idea of
scoring individual regions as either male or female rests on a conceptual
fallacy. It is thus no surprise that hardly any individuals meet this measure
of internal consistency. The way the experiment is framed practically
guarantees it.
The main problem with this framing is that
it ignores the fact that most of the variation in the measured parameters has nothing
to do with sex. This is the same situation as with height. If there
were no males or females, humans would still show a normal, bell-shaped
distribution in height. The sex difference acts on top of that, making males a little taller and females a little
shorter, on average, thus creating two, overlapping distributions.
We can’t predict a person’s height from
their sex, or vice versa, because there are not two distinct forms. What we can
say is that any given woman – whatever her actual height – would probably have
been a little taller if she were a man (but otherwise genetically unchanged).
I’m going to betray my true nerd background
here and use an analogy from Dungeons and Dragons. In this game, each player
creates a character – a Fighter or Wizard, or Thief, etc. This process begins
by defining values for six different traits: Strength, Intelligence, Wisdom,
Dexterity, Constitution and Charisma. Each of these values is determined by
rolling three 6-sided dice and adding up the values. Because there are lots of
combinations that can give values near the average and few that can give values
at the extremes, this creates a normal distribution with a range from 3-18 and
a mean value of 10.5, for each trait. So, you’ll have lots of values at 10 or
11, slightly fewer at 9 and 12, and so on, until we get to very few at 3 or 18.
Now, imagine that after we roll these
values we apply a sex modifier. A small difference, up or down, on various
traits, depending on whether the character is male or female. (In the game,
this is done depending on whether you are an elf, dwarf, hobbit, half-orc,
etc.). Let’s say +1 to strength for males and -1 to strength for females. All
that would do is shift the mean of the males to 11.5 and the mean of females to
9.5. There would still be a huge overlap. If you define 19 (the only point at
the high end with no overlap) as the “male form”, then very few males would show
it – the ones who do would have to have started at 18, just by chance.
The same applies in the brain. Say there is
some region that is slightly larger in males than in females, such that the
distribution in males extends at the extreme end to sizes beyond that seen in
any females. If a given male shows such a value, this does not mean that that
part of their brain has been extremely masculinised. It is much more likely that
they simply started at that end of the distribution to begin with, independent
of any sex effects. Being male just shifted it a little further. Likewise, those
bits of the brain that are in the middle of the distribution are not
necessarily any less masculinised. They probably just started nearer that value.
We have no idea what factors at a cellular
level give rise to the primary distribution in size of different brain regions between
individual humans and we don’t know which factors give rise to the sex
difference – these could be the same or different. The overall size
distribution could mainly reflect, say cell number, while the sex difference
could reflect growth of nerve fibres (dendrites) and number of synaptic
connections. In fact, in animals, different cellular-level parameters are
affected by sex in different parts of the brain. How these relate to crude
measures of overall volume of different brain regions is largely unknown. More
importantly, how the volume of various brain regions relates to differences in their function is almost completely
unknown.
So, from that perspective, the imaging
results of Joel et al do not support either an anatomical or a functional
male-female brain mosaic. Nor do they contradict the idea that there exists a
“male” brain and a “female” brain, overall. In fact, the very same data
strongly support that idea, when analysed in a multivariate fashion (taking
multiple differences into account at the same time).
In my original blog, I stated:
A quick look at panel
E of the figure shows that… most of the female brains showed a mostly female
pattern (lots of pink) while most of the male brains showed a mostly male
pattern (lots of blue – don’t blame me, I didn’t pick the colours!).
The group differences
are clear and highly significant. And even if very few of the males or females
are at the extreme end of the distribution for all ten of these regions,
the overall pattern suggests that you could build a very good classifier from
the volumes of these ten regions taken together, which would be quite
successful at predicting whether a given brain scan came from a male or a
female. Indeed, this would have been a far more objective test of whether MRI
volumetric differences between male and female brains are categorical or
dimensional.
This is exactly what three separate groups
rapidly did in response to Joel’s paper. Rosenblatt illustrated very clearly
how, combining information from even only two variables at the same time can
allow you to distinguish between groups (given the right conditions), even when
the distributions overlap considerably for each variable alone. (This is just
meant to illustrate the general method).
Using that kind of technique, and the data
from the paper itself, Del Giudice and colleagues built a classifier that was
69-77% accurate in distinguishing male from female brains. Rosenblatt built one
that was about 80% accurate. And Chekroud et al, using a different dataset,
built a classifier that was 90-95% accurate in distinguishing male and female
brains, when tested on a separate sample.
Rosenblatt summed up the general conclusion:
Given
our empirical evidence and the multivariate intuition depicted above, we cannot
help but disagree with the concluding statement in the abstract of Joel et al.
(1), “. . . human brains do not belong to one of two distinct categories: male
brain/female brain” or their statement that “. . .brains do not fall into two
classes, one typical of males and the other typical of females.. . .” A simple
multivariate analysis using the same data suggests quite the opposite: Brains
are indeed typically male or typically female.
Now, what this means is far from clear.
First of all, it is important to emphasise that these anatomical differences
are slight, compared to the overall underlying variation. Second, we don’t know
what the functional consequences of the differences are. None of the observed
differences has been linked to any sex difference in a behavioural or
psychological trait. Third, the existence of brain differences in adults, by
themselves, does not prove that they are all innate. (Though it should be noted
that sex differences in brain size and structure are observed even in very
young infants).
Fourth, even if all the brain differences
were clearly innate, this would not prove that all observed sex differences in behaviour are entirely biological and
innate in origin. The most likely scenario is that some behavioural traits do
show innate differences between the sexes, on average, but that these are (probably
quite strongly) amplified and reinforced by nurture and by cultural
expectations.
And finally, (and I can’t believe this has
to be said), the existence of male-typical and female-typical forms does not
make one better than the other. Nor do group average differences justify sexist
expectations of individuals – this is the very definition of prejudice. The
fact that there are small, but systematic average differences between the
brains of men and women should not in any way undermine the continuing drive
for equal treatment, equal opportunity and equal rights. We don’t all have to
be intersex to be treated equally.
This comment has been removed by the author.
ReplyDeleteI was talking to someone the other day who told me that estrogen is not the female sex hormone. I was astonished by this. He pretty much stated that estrogen does not correlate to the female sex, as it is produced by males as well. But surely if that is the case, how can we describe the phenotypical effects of estrogen as feminizing if estrogen is not the female sex hormone?
ReplyDeleteThe same question also applies for testosterone. How can we describe the phenotypical effects of testosterone as masculinising if testosterone is also produced (albeit in smaller amounts) in women? And it's produced in their ovaries, of all places!
Note: I deleted my previous comment because something went wrong with the paragraphs. This is the corrected version.
So what's the point in constantly writing about these small differences in brain's when they aren't directly linked to any sex differences in behaviour etc? None of the studies proves their own statement completely. This is just bullshit talk honestly.
ReplyDelete